power. The noble man honours in himself the powerful one, him also who has power over himself, who knows how to speak and how to keep silence, who takes pleasure in subjecting himself to severity and hardness, and has reverence for all that is severe and hard. âWotan placed a hard heart in my breast,â says an old Scandinavian Saga: it is thus rightly expressed from the soul of a proud Viking. Such a type of man is even proud of not being made for sympathy; the hero of the Saga therefore adds warningly: âHe who has not a hard heart when young, will never have one.â The noble and brave who think thus are the furthest removed from the morality which sees precisely in sympathy, or in acting for the good of others, or in desinteressement, the characteristic of the moral; faith in oneself, pride in oneself, a radical enmity and irony towards âselflessness,â belong as definitely to noble morality, as do a careless scorn and precaution in presence of sympathy and the âwarm heart.ââ âIt is the powerful who know how to honour, it is their art, their domain for invention. The profound reverence for age and for traditionâ âall law rests on this double reverenceâ âthe belief and prejudice in favour of ancestors and unfavourable to newcomers, is typical in the morality of the powerful; and if, reversely, men of âmodern ideasâ believe almost instinctively in âprogressâ and the âfuture,â and are more and more lacking in respect for old age, the ignoble origin of these âideasâ has complacently betrayed itself thereby. A morality of the ruling class, however, is more especially foreign and irritating to present-day taste in the sternness of its principle that one has duties only to oneâs equals; that one may act towards beings of a lower rank, towards all that is foreign, just as seems good to one, or âas the heart desires,â and in any case âbeyond good and evilâ: it is here that sympathy and similar sentiments can have a place. The ability and obligation to exercise prolonged gratitude and prolonged revengeâ âboth only within the circle of equalsâ âartfulness in retaliation, raffinement of the idea in friendship, a certain necessity to have enemies (as outlets for the emotions of envy, quarrelsomeness, arroganceâ âin fact, in order to be a good friend): all these are typical characteristics of the noble morality, which, as has been pointed out, is not the morality of âmodern ideas,â and is therefore at present difficult to realize, and also to unearth and disclose.â âIt is otherwise with the second type of morality, slave-morality. Supposing that the abused, the oppressed, the suffering, the unemancipated, the weary, and those uncertain of themselves should moralize, what will be the common element in their moral estimates? Probably a pessimistic suspicion with regard to the entire situation of man will find expression, perhaps a condemnation of man, together with his situation. The slave has an unfavourable eye for the virtues of the powerful; he has a skepticism and distrust, a refinement of distrust of everything âgoodâ that is there honouredâ âhe would fain persuade himself that the very happiness there is not genuine. On the other hand, those qualities which serve to alleviate the existence of sufferers are brought into prominence and flooded with light; it is here that sympathy, the kind, helping hand, the warm heart, patience, diligence, humility, and friendliness attain to honour; for here these are the most useful qualities, and almost the only means of supporting the burden of existence. Slave-morality is essentially the morality of utility. Here is the seat of the origin of the famous antithesis âgoodâ and âevilâ:â âpower and dangerousness are assumed to reside in the evil, a certain dreadfulness, subtlety, and strength, which do not admit of being despised. According to slave-morality, therefore, the âevilâ man arouses fear; according to master-morality, it is precisely the âgoodâ man who arouses fear and seeks to arouse it, while the bad man is regarded as the despicable being. The contrast attains its maximum when, in accordance with the logical consequences of slave-morality, a shade of depreciationâ âit may be slight and well-intentionedâ âat last attaches itself to the âgoodâ man of this morality; because, according to the servile mode of thought, the good man must in any case be the safe man: he is good-natured, easily deceived, perhaps a little stupid, un bonhomme. Everywhere that slave-morality gains the ascendancy, language shows a tendency to approximate the significations of the words âgoodâ and âstupid.ââ âA last fundamental difference: the desire for freedom, the instinct for happiness and the refinements of the feeling of liberty belong as necessarily to slave-morals and morality, as artifice and enthusiasm in reverence and devotion are the regular symptoms of an aristocratic mode of thinking and estimating.â âHence we can understand without further detail why love as a passionâ âit is our European specialtyâ âmust absolutely be of noble origin; as is well known, its invention is due to the Provençal poet-cavaliers, those brilliant, ingenious men of the âgai saber,â to whom Europe owes so much, and almost owes itself.
261
Vanity is one of the things which are perhaps most difficult for a noble man to understand: he will be tempted to deny it, where another kind of man thinks he sees it self-evidently. The problem for him is to represent to his mind beings who seek to arouse a good opinion of themselves which they themselves do not possessâ âand consequently also do not âdeserve,ââ âand who yet believe in this good opinion afterwards. This seems to him on the one hand such bad taste and so self-disrespectful, and on the other hand so grotesquely unreasonable, that he would like to consider vanity an exception, and is doubtful about it in most cases when it is spoken of. He will say, for instance: âI may be mistaken about my value, and on the other hand may nevertheless demand that my value should be acknowledged by others precisely as I
Comments (0)